Bourdieu (on) From Neokantian to Hegelian Critical Social Theory.pdf

(141 KB) Pobierz
444583437 UNPDF
Paul Redding
Pierre Bourdieu: From Neo-Kantian to Hegelian
Critical Social Theory
ABSTRACT
This paper challenges the commonly made claim that
the work of Pierre Bourdieu is fundamentally anti -Hegelian
in orientation. In contrast, it argues that the development
of Bourdieu’s work from its earliest structuralist through
its later ‘post-structuralist’ phase is better described in
terms of a shift from a late nineteenth century neo -
Kantian to a distinctly Hegelian post -Kantian outlook. In
his break with structuralism, Bourdieu appealed to a bod-
ily based ‘logic of practice’ to explain the binaristic logic
of Lévi-Strauss’ structuralist analyses of myth. Effectively
working within the tradition of the Durkheimian approach
to symbolic classification, Lévi-Strauss had inherited
Durkheim’s distinctly neo-Kantian understanding of the
role of categories in experience and action—an account
that conflated two forms of representation—‘intuitions’
and ‘concepts—that Kant himself had held distinct.
Bourdieu’s appeal to the role of the body’s dispositional
habitus can be considered as a retrieval of Hegel’s earlier
quite different reworking of Kant’s intuition-concept dis-
tinction in terms of distinct ‘logics’ with different forms
of ‘negation’. Bourdieu commonly acknowledged the par-
allels of his analyses of social life to those of Hegel, but
opposed Hegelianism because he believed that Hegel
had remained entrapped within the dynamics of
mythopoeic thought. In contrast, Durkheim and Lévi-
Strauss, he claimed, by instituting a science of myth, had
Critical Horizons 6:1 (2005)
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2005
444583437.002.png
broken with it.This criticism of Hegel, however, relies on an understanding of his philosophy that
has been rejected by many contemporary Hegel scholars, and without it, the gap separating
Hegel and Bourdieu narrows dramatically.
KEY WORDS: Bourdieu, Hegel, Durkheim, Structuralism, Post-Structuralism, Neo-Kantianism
Initially, the idea of linking the work of French ethnologist-sociologist Pierre
Bourdieu to Hegel may seem surprising. Having emerged from the generation
of structuralist thinkers in the 1960’s, Bourdieu can thereby be regarded to
have come from an intellectual movement that virtually defined itself in oppo-
sition to an ‘Hegelian humanism’ exemplified by Sartre. For Bourdieu, as for
contemporaries like Foucault or Althusser, approaches to the history of the
sciences found in epistemological thinkers such as Gaston Bachelard and
George Canguilhem 1 replaced that humanistic variant of the Hegelian story
of the teleological emergence of the essentially universal human subject.
Moreover, in ethnography itself, Lévi-Strauss had explicitly opposed his struc-
turalist thought to Sartre’s version of Hegelian humanism, 2 and identified his
approach as a type of “Kantianism without a transcendental subject.” 3
Indeed, along with Lévi-Strauss, Bourdieu can be thought of as continuing
some of the features of late nineteenth-century French neo-Kantianism, thereby
establishing a route ‘back to Kant’ which largely bypassed Hegel and other
German idealists. Crucially, both Lévi-Strauss and Bourdieu were influenced
by Émile Durkheim whose work showed strong neo-Kantian influences. 4 And
while Bourdieu’s ‘structuralism’ might have been relatively short lived, 5 his
‘post-structuralist’ work looks no friendlier to Hegelianism. 6 What we might
regard as the first recognisably ‘Bourdieuan’ work, Esquisse d’une Théorie de
la Pratique , published in 1972, 7 had been conceived as a critique of Lévi-
Strauss, but with this Bourdieu seemed to deepen his earlier critique of the
‘academic aristocratism’ of any totalising philosophy, drawing upon further
types of philosophical ‘anti-philosophers’—‘ordinary language’ philosophers
such as Wittgenstein and Austin, for example—who seem equally distant
from Hegel’s systematising. Even the Marxist elements in Bourdieu’s work
are commonly said to have a strikingly anti-Hegelian nature. 8
After his turn away from structuralism, Bourdieu criticised Lévi-Strauss’
approach as suffering from a tendency to intellectualise the objects of its own
field of study—the field of mythopoeic thought . Indeed, structuralism was seen
184 • Paul Redding
444583437.003.png
as suffering from a form of logicism akin to Hegel’s, Bourdieu comparing Lévi-
Strauss’ inquiry into the “universal laws which govern the unconscious
activities of the mind” to Hegel’s account of the universal spirit that “thinks
itself.” 9 While Lévi-Strauss had looked to the structure of myth and ritual to
disclose the universal structures of human thought, from Bourdieu’s post-
structuralist perspective, an examination of the context within which
mythopoeic thought was enacted revealed its ‘logic’ to be generated not from
some underlying formal structure, nor from any mythopoeic version of ‘tran-
scendental consciousness’, but from an ensemble of unconscious practically
oriented bodily dispositions—what Bourdieu termed ‘habitus’—responsive
to the demands of varying and particular circumstances within a socially
encoded environment. 10
Bourdieu’s move beyond structuralism can easily be seen as strengthening
and deepening certain Kantian dimensions of his thought, as he was now
concerned with criticising the hypostatisation of a form of thought—that of the
scientific ethnologist—beyond the conditions of its own functioning. Like the
pre-Copernican cosmologist, the scholastic ethnologist appeared to project
the conditions of his own experience onto the object of inquiry. Bourdieu’s
response was thus to extend Kant’s critique of pure reason into what he called
a ‘critique of scholastic reason’. And yet this familiar anti-Hegelian reading of
Bourdieu, I suggest, is confounded by the remarkable points of convergence
one finds within Bourdieu’s work—often signalled by Bourdieu himself—
with the thought of Hegel. It is such points of convergence that I want to
broach here, first, that between Bourdieu’s ‘logic of practice’ and Hegel’s
account of the structure of what can be termed ‘immediate thought’, and
next, that between the respective accounts each give of the conditions under
which systematic ‘reflective’ thought can break with the socially conditioned
logic of practice. This is done not for the purpose of reducing Bourdieu’s
remarkably innovative work to the status of repetition of a thinker regarded
as having brought intellectual history to a close, but more to question the
degree to which Hegel himself can be reduced to the image of that philosopher
against which Bourdieu and his generation had reacted.
Pierre Bourdieu: From Neo-Kantian to Hegelian Critical Social Theory • 185
444583437.004.png
I. Practical versus Theoretical Logic and the Critique of Scholastic
Reason
After his break with structuralist formalism, Bourdieu came to regard Lévi-
Strauss’ intellectualising analyses of mythopoeic thought as exemplifying a
danger implicit in the very move which liberates scientific thought from the
constraints of everyday life: the danger of a ‘scholastic forgetting’ of the his-
torical specificity of those conditions allowing the reflexively epistemic
orientation to the world characteristic of scholarship itself. While still main-
taining his earlier positive ‘Bachelardian’ stance towards the establishment
of the sciences in their break with the schemas of everyday life, Bourdieu’s
attitude was now tempered by a sensitivity to the ambiguity of such episte-
mological breaks: “The fundamental ambiguity of the scholastic universes and
of all their productions... lies in the fact that their apartness from the world
of production is both a liberatory break and a disconnection, a potentially
crippling separation.” 11
In order to capture the peculiarity of the theoretical attitude and the conditions
that underlie its emergence in various realms, as well as its inherent ambiguity,
Bourdieu employed the notion of the ‘ skholè ’. Exploiting the etymological
connection between scholarship and leisure, Bourdieu used this concept to
refer to those historically created social contexts, which “liberated from practical
occupations and preoccupations,” were able to provide the cultural spaces
for the development of the type of scholarly/scholastic linguistic practice. For
example, within the school it is “studious leisure” which becomes “the pre-
condition for scholastic exercises and activities removed from immediate
necessity, such as sport, play, the production and contemplation of works of
art and all forms of gratuitous speculation with no other end than themselves.”
These historically specific contexts liberating an activity from the immediate
demands of economic and social necessity in turn foster the “scholastic dis-
position which inclines it possessors to suspend the demands of the situation,
the constraints of economic and social necessity, and the urgencies it imposes
or the ends it proposes” to meet the demands of detached and disinterested
inquiry. 12
More specifically concerned with the emergence of objective thought about
the social field , Bourdieu’s telling of the story of the epistemological rupture
is further marked by the details of his own ethnographically derived account
186 • Paul Redding
444583437.005.png
of the form of thought with which the scholarly language game breaks and
with which it is to be contrasted— mythopoeic thought . Following Durkheim
and Mauss, 13 Bourdieu understands human practices as needing the articulation
provided by socially generated symbolic systems that, in pre-modern societies,
are objectified and transmitted in ritual and myth. Such mythopoeic thought
thus reflects and reproduces just those types of “primitive classification” struc-
turing social activity within pre-modern communities—those systems of
“inseparably cognitive and evaluative structures that organise perception of
the world and action in the world in accordance with the objective structures
of a given state of the social world.” 14 But going beyond Durkheim’s neo-
Kantian formalism and in the direction of Marx, Bourdieu draws attention
to the role played by such classifications in the articulation of relations of
domination . It is in virtue of the evaluative dimension of such differences insti-
tuted in the world that they thereby articulate a type of social domination
via a “symbolic violence” which constrains by neither overt force nor reason,
but by something in between. 15
The emergence of philosophy in classical Greece, which provides the skholè
with its “ideal type,” exemplifies such a break with systems of mythopoeic
thought. There “myths and rites ceased to be practical acts of belief... and
became instead matter for theoretical astonishment and questioning, or objects
of hermeneutic rivalry.” 16 But as an ethnologist Bourdieu was interested in the
break from mythical thought in the context of the inquiry into myth itself —a
break, he claimed, which was not achieved until the work of Durkheim and
Mauss, and, importantly, Lévi-Strauss. It was Lévi-Strauss’ achievement,
Bourdieu tells us, to have “provided the means of completing the abandonment
of recourse to the mythological mode of thought in the science of mytholo-
gies... by resolutely taking this mode of thought as his object instead of
setting it to work, as native mythologists always do, in order to provide a
mythological solution to mythological problems.” 17 And yet, as we have seen,
in his structuralist search for some universal grammar or ‘logic’ underlying
the outputs of mythical thought, Lévi-Strauss had projected onto his subjects
the disengaged dispositions of his own scholastic context—forgetting, and
thereby universalising, the historical specificity of his own intellectual practice.
Following his break with structuralism, in works like Esquisse d’une Théorie
de la Pratique and Le sens Pratique , Bourdieu attempted to reinterpret the type
Pierre Bourdieu: From Neo-Kantian to Hegelian Critical Social Theory • 187
444583437.001.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin