An Essay In Aid Of A Grammar Of Assent by John Henry Newman.doc

(2067 KB) Pobierz
The Project Gutenberg EBook of An Essay In Aid Of A Grammar Of Assent by

The Project Gutenberg EBook of An Essay In Aid Of A Grammar Of Assent by

John Henry Newman

 

 

 

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no

restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under

the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or

online at http://www.gutenberg.org/license

 

 

 

Title: An Essay In Aid Of A Grammar Of Assent

 

Author: John Henry Newman

 

Release Date: October 1, 2010 [Ebook #34022]

 

Language: English

 

Character set encoding: UTF8

 

 

***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN ESSAY IN AID OF A GRAMMAR OF ASSENT***

 

 

 

 

 

                                 An Essay

 

                                In Aid Of

 

                           A Grammar Of Assent.

 

                                    by

 

                            John Henry Newman,

 

                             Of the Oratory.

 

       Non in dialecticà complacuit Deo salvum facere populum suum.

 

                               ST. AMBROSE.

 

                                 London:

 

                           Burns, Oates, & Co.

 

            17 & 18, Portman Street, and 63, Paternoster Row.

 

                                   1874

 

 

 

 

 

CONTENTS

 

 

Dedication.

Part I. Assent And Apprehension.

   Chapter I. Modes Of Holding And Apprehending Propositions.

      § 1. Modes of Holding Propositions.

      § 2. Modes of apprehending Propositions.

   Chapter II. Assent Considered As Apprehensive.

   Chapter III. The Apprehension Of Propositions.

   Chapter IV. Notional And Real Assent.

      § 1. Notional Assents.

      § 2. Real Assents.

      § 3. Notional and Real Assents Contrasted.

   Chapter V. Apprehension And Assent In The Matter Of Religion.

      § 1. Belief in One God.

      § 2. Belief in the Holy Trinity.

      § 3. Belief in Dogmatic Theology.

Part II. Assent And Inference.

   Chapter VI. Assent Considered As Unconditional.

      § 1. Simple Assent.

      § 2. Complex Assent.

   Chapter VII. Certitude.

      § 1. Assent and Certitude Contrasted.

      § 2. Indefectibility of Certitude.

   Chapter VIII. Inference.

      § 1. Formal Inference.

      § 2. Informal Inference.

      § 3. Natural Inference.

   Chapter IX. The Illative Sense.

      § 1. The Sanction of the Illative Sense.

      § 2. The Nature of the Illative Sense.

      § 3. The Range of the Illative Sense.

   Chapter X. Inference And Assent In The Matter Of Religion.

      § 1. Natural Religion.

      § 2. Revealed Religion.

Note.

Footnotes

 

 

 

 

 

 

DEDICATION.

 

 

To

 

Edward Bellasis,

 

Serjeant At Law,

 

In Remembrance

 

Of A Long, Equable, Sunny Friendship;

 

In Gratitude

 

For Continual Kindnesses Shown To Me,

 

For An Unwearied Zeal In My Behalf,

 

For A Trust In Me Which Has Never Wavered,

 

And A Prompt, Effectual Succour And Support

 

In Times Of Special Trial,

 

From His Affectionate

 

J. H. N.

 

_February 21, 1870._

 

 

 

 

 

PART I. ASSENT AND APPREHENSION.

 

 

 

 

Chapter I. Modes Of Holding And Apprehending Propositions.

 

 

 

§ 1. Modes of Holding Propositions.

 

 

1. Propositions (consisting of a subject and predicate united by the

copula) may take a categorical, conditional, or interrogative form.

 

(1) An interrogative, when they ask a Question, (e. g. Does Free-trade

benefit the poorer classes?) and imply the possibility of an affirmative

or negative resolution of it.

 

(2) A conditional, when they express a Conclusion (e. g. Free-trade

therefore benefits the poorer classes), and both imply, and imply their

dependence on, other propositions.

 

(3) A categorical, when they simply make an Assertion (e. g. Free-trade

does benefit), and imply the absence of any condition or reservation of

any kind, looking neither before nor behind, as resting in themselves and

being intrinsically complete.

 

These three modes of shaping a proposition, distinct as they are from each

other, follow each other in natural sequence. A proposition, which starts

with being a Question, may become a Conclusion, and then be changed into

an Assertion; but it has of course ceased to be a question, so far forth

as it has become a conclusion, and has rid itself of its argumentative

form—that is, has ceased to be a conclusion,—so far forth as it has become

an assertion. A question has not yet got so far as to be a conclusion,

though it is the necessary preliminary of a conclusion; and an assertion

has got beyond being a mere conclusion, though it is the natural issue of

a conclusion. Their correlation is the measure of their distinction one

from another.

 

No one is likely to deny that a question is distinct both from a

conclusion and from an assertion; and an assertion will be found to be

equally distinct from a conclusion. For, if we rest our affirmation on

arguments, this shows that we are not asserting; and, when we assert, we

do not argue. An assertion is as distinct from a conclusion, as a word of

command is from a persuasion or recommendation. Command and assertion, as

such, both of them, in their different ways, dispense with, discard,

ignore, antecedents of any kind, though antecedents may have been a _sine

quâ non_ condition of their being elicited. They both carry with them the

pretension of being personal acts.

 

In insisting on the intrinsic distinctness of these three modes of putting

a proposition, I am not maintaining that they may not co-exist as regards

one and the same subject. For what we have already concluded, we may, if

we will, make a question of; and what we are asserting, we may of course

conclude over again. We may assert, to one man, and conclude to another,

and ask of a third; still, when we assert, we do not conclude, and, when

we assert or conclude, we do not question.

 

2. The internal act of holding propositions is for the most part analogous

to the external act of enunciating them; as there are three ways of

enunciating, so are there three ways of holding them, each corresponding

to each. These three mental acts are Doubt, Inference, and Assent. A

question is the expression of a doubt; a conclusion is the expression of

an act of inference; and an assertion is the expression of an act of

assent. To doubt, for instance, is not to see one’s way to hold that

Free-trade is or that it is not a benefit; to infer, is to hold on

sufficient grounds that Free-trade may, must, or should be a benefit; to

assent to the proposition, is to hold that Free-trade is a benefit.

 

Moreover, propositions, while they are the material of these three

enunciations, are the objects of the three corresponding mental acts; and

as without a proposition, there cannot be a question, conclusion, or

assertion, so without a proposition there is nothing to doubt about,

nothing to infer, nothing to assent to. Mental acts of whatever kind

presuppose their objects.

 

And, since the three enunciations are distinct from each other, therefore

the three mental acts also, Doubt, Inference, and Assent, are, with

reference to one and the same proposition, distinct from each other; else,

why should their several enunciations be distinct? And indeed it is very

evident, that, so far forth as we infer, we do not doubt, and that, when

we assent, we are not inferring, and, when we doubt, we cannot assent.

 

And in fact, these three modes of entertaining propositions,—doubting

them, inferring them, assenting to them, are so distinct in their action,

that, when they are severally carried out into the intellectual habits of

an individual, they become the principles and notes of three distinct

states or characters of mind. For instance, in the case of Revealed

Religion, according as one or other of these is paramount within him, a

man is a sceptic as regards it; or a philosopher, thinking it more or less

probable considered as a conclusion of reason; or he has an unhesitating

faith in it, and is recognized as a believer. If he simply disbelieves, or

dissents, he is assenting to the contradictory of the thesis, viz. that

there is no Revelation.

 

Many minds of course there are, which are not under the predominant

influence of any one of the three. Thus men are to be found of

irreflective, impulsive, unsettled, or again of acute minds, who do not

know what they believe and what they do not, and who may be by turns

sceptics, inquirers, or believers; who doubt, assent, infer, and doubt

again, according to the circumstances of the season. Nay further, in all

minds there is a certain coexistence of these distinct acts; that is, of

two of them, for we can at once infer and assent, though we cannot at once

either assent or infer and also doubt. Indeed, in a multitude of cases we

infer truths, or apparent truths, before, and while, and after we assent

to them.

 

Lastly, it cannot be denied that these three acts are all natural to the

mind; I mean, that, in exercising them, we are not violating the laws of

our nature, as if they were in themselves an extravagance or weakness, but

are acting according to it, according to its legitimate constitution.

Undoubtedly, it is possible, it is common, in the particular case, to err

in the exercise of Doubt, of Inference, and of Assent; that is, we may be

withholding a judgment about propositions on which we have the means of

coming to some definitive conclusion; or we may be assenting to

propositions which we ought to receive only on the credit of their

premisses, or again to keep ourselves in suspense about; but such errors

of the individual belong to the individual, not to his nature, and cannot

avail to forfeit for him his natural right, under proper circumstances, to

doubt, or to infer, or to assent. We do but fulfil our nature in doubting,

inferring, and assenting; and our duty is, not to abstain from the

exercise of any function of our nature, but to do what is in itself right

rightly.

 

3. So far in general:—in this Essay I treat of propositions only in their

bearing upon concrete matter, and I am mainly concerned with Assent; with

Inference, in its relation to Assent, and only such inference as is not

demonstration; with Doubt hardly at all. I dismiss Doubt with one

observation. I have here spoken of it simply as a suspense of mind, in

which sense of the word, to have “no doubt” about a thesis is equivalent

to one or other of the two remaining acts, either to inferring it or else

assenting to it. However, the word is often taken to mean the deliberate

recognition of a thesis as being uncertain; in this sense Doubt is nothing

else than an assent, viz. an assent to a proposition at variance with the

thesis, as I have already noticed in the case of Disbelief.

 

Confining myself to the subject of Assent and Inference, I observe two

points of contrast between them.

 

The first I have already noted. Assent is unconditional; else, it is not

really represented by assertion. Inference is conditional, because a

conclusion at least implies the assumption of premisses, and still more,

because in concrete matter, on which I am engaged, demonstration is

impossible.

 

The second has regard to the apprehension necessary for holding a

proposition. We cannot assent to a proposition, without some intelligent

apprehension of it; whereas we need not understand it at all in order to

infer it. We cannot give our assent to the proposition that “x is z,” till

we are told something about one or other of the terms; but we can infer,

if “x is y, and y is z, that x is z,” whether we know the meaning of x and

z or no.

 

These points of contrast and their results will come before us in due

course: here, for a time leaving the consideration of the modes of holding

propositions, I proceed to inquire into what is to be understood by

apprehending them.

 

 

 

§ 2. Modes of apprehending Propositions.

 

 

By our apprehension of propositions I mean our imposition of a sense on

the terms of which they are composed. Now what do the terms of a

proposition, the subject and predicate, stand for? Sometimes they stand

for certain ideas existing in our own minds, and for nothing outside of

them; sometimes for things simply external to us, brought home to us

through the experiences and informations we have of them. All things in

the exterior world are unit and individual, and are nothing else; but the

mind not only contemplates those unit realities, as they exist, but has

the gift, by an act of creation, of bringing before it abstractions and

generalizations, which have no existence, no counterpart, out of it.

 

Now there are propositions, in which one or both of the terms are common

nouns, as standing for what is abstract, general, and non-existing, such

as “Man is an animal, some men are learned, an Apostle is a creation of

Christianity, a line is length without breadth, to err is human, to

forgive divine.” These I shall call notional propositions, and the

apprehension with which we infer or assent to them, notional.

 

And there are other propositions, which are composed of singular nouns,

and of which the terms stand for things external to us, unit and

individual, as “Philip was the father of Alexander,” “the earth goes round

the sun,” “the Apostles first preached to the Jews;” and these I shall

call real propositions, and their apprehension real.

 

There are then two apprehensions or interpretations to which propositions

may be subjected, notional and real.

 

Next I observe, that the same proposition may admit of both of these

interpretations at once, having a notional sense as used by one man, and a

real as used by another. Thus a schoolboy may perfectly apprehend, and

construe with spirit, the poet’s words, “Dum Capitolium scandet cum tacitâ

Virgine Pontifex;” he has seen steep hills, flights of steps, and

processions; he knows what enforced silence is; also he knows all about

the Pontifex Maximus, and the Vestal Virgins; he has an abstract hold upon

every word of the description, yet without the words therefore bringing

before him at all the living image which they would light up in the mind

of a contemporary of the poet, who had seen the fact described, or of a

modern historian who had duly informed himself in the religious phenomena,

and by meditation had realized the Roman ceremonial, of the age of

Augustus. Again, “Dulce et decorum est pro patriâ mori,” is a mere

common-place, a terse expression of abstractions in the mind of the poet

himself, if Philippi is to be the index of his patriotism, whereas it

would be the record of experiences, a sovereign dogma, a grand aspiration,

inflaming the imagination, piercing the heart, of a Wallace or a Tell.

 

As the multitude of common nouns have originally been singular, it is not

surprising that many of them should so remain still in the apprehension of

particular individuals. In the proposition “Sugar is sweet,” the predicate

is a common noun as used by those who have compared sugar in their

thoughts with honey or glycerine; but it may be the only distinctively

sweet thing in the experience of a child, and may be used by him as a noun

singular. The first time that he tastes sugar, if his nurse says, “Sugar

is sweet” in a notional sense, meaning by sugar, lump-sugar, powdered,

brown, and candied, and by sweet, a specific flavour or scent which is

found in many articles of food and many flowers, he may answer in a real

sense, and in an individual proposition “Sugar is sweet,” meaning “this

sugar is this sweet thing.”

 

Thirdly, in the same mind and at the same time, the same proposition may

express both what is notional and what is real. When a lecturer in

mechanics or chemistry shows to his class by experiment some physical

fact, he and his hearers at once enunciate it as an individual thing

before their eyes, and also as generalized by their minds into a law of

nature. When Virgil says, “Varium et mutabile semper fœmina,” he both sets

before his readers what he means to be a general truth, and at the same

time applies it individually to the instance of Dido. He expresses at once

a notion and a fact.

 

Of these two modes of apprehending propositions, notional and real, real

is the stronger; I mean by stronger the more vivid and forcible. It is so

to be accounted for the very reason that it is concerned with what is

either real or taken for real; f...

Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin