Plantinga; The ontological argument.pdf

(88 KB) Pobierz
113041168 UNPDF
Alvin Plantinga
The Ontological Argument
Page 1/15
The Ontological Argument
ALVIN PLANTINGA
[1] The third theistic argument I wish to discuss is the famous "ontological argument" first
formulated by Anselm of Canterbury in the eleventh century. This argument for the
existence of God has fascinated philosophers ever since Anselm first stated it. Few people, I
should think, have been brought to belief in God by means of this argument; nor has it
played much of a role in strengthening and confirming religious faith. At first sight Anselm's
argument is remarkably unconvincing if not downright irritating; it looks too much like a
parlor puzzle or word magic. And yet nearly every major philosopher from the time of
Anselm to the present has had something to say about it; this argument has a long and
illustrious line of defenders extending to the present. Indeed, the last few years have seen a
remarkable flurry of interest in it among philosophers. What accounts for its fascination?
Not, I think, its religious significance, although that can be underrated. Perhaps there are
two reasons for it. First, many of the most knotty and difficult problems in philosophy meet
in this argument. Is existence a property? Are existential propositions -- propositions of the
form x exists -- ever necessarily true? Are existential propositions about what they seem to
be about? Are there, in any respectable sense of "are," some objects that do not exist? If
so, do they have any properties? Can they be compared with things that do exist? These
issues and a hundred others arise in connection with Anselm's argument. And second,
although the argument certainly looks at first sight as if it ought to be unsound, it is
profoundly difficult to say what, exactly, is wrong with it. Indeed, I do not believe that any
philosopher has ever given a cogent and conclusive refutation of the ontological argument in
its various forms.
[2] At first sight, [Anselm's] argument smacks of trumpery and deceit; but suppose we look
at it a bit more closely. Its essentials are contained in these words:
And assuredly that, than which nothing greater can be conceived, cannot exist in the
understanding alone. For suppose it exists in the understanding alone; then it can be
conceived to exist in reality; which is greater.
Therefore, if that, than which nothing greater can be conceived, exists in the
understanding alone, the very being, than which nothing greater can be conceived, is
one, than which a greater can be conceived. But obviously this is impossible. Hence
there is no doubt that there exists a being, than which nothing greater can be
conceived, and it exists both in the understanding and in reality.
[3] How can we outline this argument? It is best construed, I think, as a reductio ad
absurdum argument. In a reductio you prove a given proposition p by showing that its
denial, not-p , leads to (or more strictly, entails) a contradiction or some other kind of
absurdity. Anselm's argument can be seen as an attempt to deduce an absurdity from the
proposition that there is no God. If we use the term "God" as an abbreviation for Anselm's
phrase "the being than which nothing greater can be conceived," then the argument seems
to go approximately as follows: Suppose
(1) God exists in the understanding but not in reality. (reductio assumption)
(2) Existence in reality is greater than existence in the understanding alone.
(premise)
Alvin Plantinga
The Ontological Argument
Page 2/15
(3) God's existence in reality is conceivable. (premise)
(4) If God did exist in reality, then He would be greater than He is. [from (1) and
(2)]
(5) It is conceivable that there is a being greater than God is. [(3) and (4)]
(6) It is conceivable that there be a being greater than the being than which nothing
greater can be conceived. [(5) by the definition of "God"]
[4] But surely (6) is absurd and self-contradictory; how could we conceive of a being
greater than the being than which none greater can be conceived? So we may conclude that
(7) It is false that God exists in the understanding but not in reality.
[5] It follows that if God exists in the understanding, He also exists in reality; but clearly
enough He does exist in the understanding, as even the fool will testify; therefore, He exists
in reality as well.
[6] Now when Anselm says that a being exists in the understanding, we may take him, I
think, as saying that someone has thought of or thought about that being. When he says
that something exists in reality, on the other hand, he means to say simply that the thing in
question really does exist. And when he says that a certain state of affairs is conceivable, he
means to say, I believe, that this state of affairs is possible in our broadly logical sense,
there is a possible world in which it obtains. This means that step (3) above may be put
more perspicuously as
(3') It is possible that God exists
and step (6) as
(6') It is possible that there be a being greater than the being than which it is not
possible that there be a greater.
[7] An interesting feature of this argument is that all of its premises are necessarily true if
true at all. (1) is the assumption from which Anselm means to deduce a contradiction. (2) is
a premise, and presumably necessarily true in Anselm's view; and (3) is the only remaining
premise (the other items are consequences of preceding steps); it says of some other
proposition (God exists) that it is possible. Propositions which thus ascribe a modality --
possibility, necessity, contingency -- to another proposition are themselves either
necessarily true or necessarily false. So all the premises of the argument are, if true at all,
necessarily true. And hence if the premises of this argument are true, then [provided that
(6) is really inconsistent] a contradiction can be deduced from (1) together with necessary
propositions; this means that (1) entails a contradiction and is, therefore, necessarily false.
Alvin Plantinga
The Ontological Argument
Page 3/15
1. Kant's Objection
[8] The most famous and important objection to the ontological argument is contained in
Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason . Kant begins his criticism as follows:
If, in an identical proposition, we reject the predicate while retaining the subject,
contradiction results; and I therefore say that the former belongs necessarily to the
latter. But if we reject the subject and predicate alike, there is no contradiction; for
nothing is then left that can be contradicted. To posit a triangle, and yet to reject its
three angles, is self-contradictory; but there is no contradiction in rejecting the
triangle together with its three angles. The same holds true of the concept of an
absolutely necessary being. If its existence is rejected, we reject the thing itself with
all its predicates; and no question of contradiction can then arise. There is nothing
outside it that would then be contradicted, since the necessity of the thing is not
supposed to be derived from anything external; nor is there anything internal that
would be contradicted, since in rejecting the thing itself we have at the same time
rejected all its internal properties. "God is omnipotent" is a necessary judgment. The
omnipotence cannot be rejected if we posit a Deity, that is, an infinite being; for the
two concepts are identical. But if we say "There is no God," neither the omnipotence
nor any other of its predicates is given; they are one and all rejected together with
the subject, and there is therefore not the least contradiction in such a judgment...
For I cannot form the least concept of a thing which, should it be rejected with all its
predicates, leaves behind a contradiction.
[9] One characteristic feature of Anselm's argument, as we have seen, is that if successful,
it establishes that God exists is a necessary proposition. Here Kant is apparently arguing
that no existential proposition -- one that asserts the existence of something or other -- is
necessarily true; the reason, he says, is that no contra-existential (the denial of an
existential) is contradictory or inconsistent. But in which of our several senses of
inconsistent? What he means to say, I believe, is that no existential proposition is necessary
in the broadly logical sense. And this claim has been popular with philosophers ever since.
But why, exactly, does Kant think it's true? What is the argument? When we take a careful
look at the purported reasoning, it looks pretty unimpressive; it's hard to make out an
argument at all. The conclusion would apparently be this: if we deny the existence of
something or other, we can't be contradicting ourselves; no existential proposition is
necessary and no contra-existential is impossible. Why not? Well, if we say, for example,
that God does not exist, then says Kant, "There is nothing outside it (i.e., God) that would
then be contradicted, since the necessity of the thing is not supposed to be derived from
anything external; nor is there anything internal that would be contradicted, since in
rejecting the thing itself we have at the same time rejected all its internal properties."
[10] But how is this even relevant? The claim is that God does not exist can't be necessarily
false. What could be meant, in this context, by saying that there's nothing "outside of" God
that would be contradicted if we denied His existence? What would contradict a proposition
like God does not exist is some other proposition -- God does exist , for example. Kant
seems to think that if the proposition in question were necessarily false, it would have to
contradict, not a proposition, but some object external to God -- or else contradict some
internal part or aspect or property of God. But this certainly looks like confusion; it is
propositions that contradict each other; they aren't contradicted by objects or parts, aspects
or properties of objects. Does he mean instead to be speaking of propositions about things
external to God, or about his aspects or parts or properties? But clearly many such
Alvin Plantinga
The Ontological Argument
Page 4/15
propositions do contradict God does not exist ; an example would be the world was created
by God . Does he mean to say that no true proposition contradicts God does not exist? No,
for that would be to affirm the nonexistence of God, an affirmation Kant is by no means
prepared to make.
[11] So this passage is an enigma. Either Kant was confused or else he expressed himself
very badly indeed. And either way we don't have any argument for the claim that contra-
existential propositions can't be inconsistent. This passage seems to be no more than an
elaborate and confused way of asserting this claim.
[12] The heart of Kant's objection to the ontological argument, however, is contained in the
following passage:
"Being" is obviously not a real predicate; that is, it is not a concept of something
which could be added to the concept of a thing. It is merely the positing of a thing,
or of certain determinations, as existing in themselves. Logically, it is merely the
copula of a judgment. The proposition "God is omnipotent" contains two concepts,
each of which has its object -- God and omnipotence . The small word "is" adds no
new predicate, but only serves to posit the predicate in its relation to the subject. If,
now, we take the subject (God) with all its predicates (among which is
omnipotence), and say "God is," or "There is a God," we attach no new predicate to
the concept of God, but only posit it as an object that stands in relation to my
concept. The content of both must be one and the same; nothing can have been
added to the concept, which expresses merely what is possible, by my thinking its
object (through the expression "it is") as given absolutely. Otherwise stated, the real
contains no more than the merely possible. A hundred real thalers does not contain
the least coin more than a hundred possible thalers. For as the latter signify the
concept and the former the object and the positing of the concept, should the former
contain more than the latter, my concept would not, in that case, express the whole
object, and would not therefore be an adequate concept of it. My financial position,
however, is affected very differently by a hundred real thalers than it is by the mere
concept of them (that is, of the possibility). For the object, as it actually exists, is not
analytically contained in my concept, but is added to my concept (which is a
determination of my state) synthetically; and yet the conceived hundred thalers are
not themselves in the least increased through thus acquiring existence outside my
concept.
By whatever and by however many predicates we may think a thing -- even if we
completely determine it -- we do not make the least addition to the thing when we
further declare that this thing is. Otherwise it would not be exactly the same thing
that exists, but something more than we had thought in the concept: and we could
not, therefore, say that the object of my concept exists. If we think in a thing every
feature of reality except one, the missing reality is not added by my saying that this
defective thing exists.
[13] Now how, exactly is all this relevant to Anselm's argument? Perhaps Kant means to
make point that we could put by saying that it's not possible to define things into existence.
(People sometimes suggest that the ontological argument is just such an attempt to define
God into existence.) And this claim is somehow connected with Kant's famous but
perplexing dictum that being (or existence) is not a real predicate or property. But how shall
we understand Kant here? What does it mean to say that existence isn't (or is) a real
property?
Alvin Plantinga
The Ontological Argument
Page 5/15
[14] Apparently Kant thinks this is equivalent to or follows from what he puts variously as
"the real contains no more than the merely possible"; "the content of both (i.e., concept
and object) must be one and the same"; "being is not the concept of something that could
be added to the concept of thing," and so on. But what does all this mean? And how does it
bear on the ontological argument? Perhaps Kant is thinking along the following lines. In
defining a concept -- bachelor, let's say, or prime number -- one lists a number of
properties that are severally necessary and jointly sufficient for the concept's applying to
something. That is, the concept applies to a given thing only if that thing has each of the
listed properties, and if thing does have them all, then the concept in question applies to it.
So, for example, to define the concept bachelor we list such properties as being unmarried,
being male, being over the age of twenty-five, and the like. Take any one of these
properties: a thing is a bachelor only if it has it, and if a thing has all of them, then it follows
that it is a bachelor.
[15] Now suppose you have a concept C that has application contingently if at all. That is to
say, it is not necessarily true that there are things to which this concept applies. The
concept bachelor would be an example; the proposition there are bachelors , while true, is
obviously not necessarily true. And suppose P1, P2, ... , Pn , are the properties jointly
sufficient and severally necessary for something's falling under C . Then C can be defined as
follows:
A thing x is an instance of C (i.e., C applies to x ) if and only if x has P1, P2, ..., Pn.
[16] Perhaps Kant's point is this. There is a certain kind of mistake here we may be tempted
to make. Suppose P1..., Pn are the defining properties for the concept bachelor. We might
try to define a new concept superbachelor by adding existence to P1 ,...,Pn . That is, we
might say
x is a superbachelor if and only if x has P1 - Pn , and x exists.
[17] Then (as we might mistakenly suppose) just as it is a necessary truth that bachelors
are unmarried, so it is a necessary truth that superbachelors exist. And in this way it looks
as if we've defined super-bachelors into existence.
[18] But of course this is a mistake, and perhaps that is Kant's point. For while indeed it is a
necessary truth that bachelors are unmarried, what this means is that the proposition
(8) Everything that is a bachelor is unmarried
is necessarily true.
[19] Similarly, then,
(9) Everything that is a superbachelor exists
will be necessarily true. But obviously it doesn't follow that there are any superbachelors. All
that follows is that
(10) All the superbachelors there are exist.
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin