Nadelhoffer; On The Importance of Saying Only What You Believe in the Socratic Dialogues.pdf

(59 KB) Pobierz
On The Importance of Saying Only What You Believe in the Socratic Dialogues
On The Importance of Saying Only What You Believe in the Socratic Dialogues
Thomas Nadelhoffer
Introduction:
On several occasions during the so-called Socratic dialogues, we find Socrates
admonishing his interlocutors to say—or assent to— only things that they honestly believe
to be true . Socrates seems so adamant about this “demand for sincerity” 1 that at least one
commentator has gone so far as to call it a “standing rule” of the Socratic elenchus that is
“generally taken for granted, mentioned only when there is a special need to bring it to
the interlocutor’s notice.” 2 However, there are a few occasions where Socrates curiously
proceeds without the interlocutor’s genuine assent to the propositions under discussion—
e.g. with Protagoras ( Pr . 333b-c), with Callicles ( G . 499b4-c6, 501c7-8, and from 505c5
on), and with Thrasymachus ( R. I. 349a9-b1 and from 350e1 and on). In this essay, I am
going to offer an explanation of Socrates’ occasional willingness to wave what Vlastos
calls the “say what you believe” requirement. 3 In doing so, I will first briefly discuss the
methods and goals of the Socratic elenchus in order to get a clear picture of Socrates’
motivation for insisting that interlocutors advance only theses they sincerely believe (§I),
before examining the passages where Socrates either fails to enforce the honesty clause
or explicitly waives it altogether (§II). Then, after considering how two commentators—
viz. Gregory Vlastos and John Beversluis—have unsuccessfully attempted to explain
Socrates’ inconsistent behavior (§III), I will present my own analysis of his puzzling
inconsistency (§IV).
I: The Socratic Elenchus—Method and Goal
On Socrates’ view, philosophizing is the activity of examining and investigating
not only our beliefs, but the lives we lead as well. 4 Viewing himself as a gadfly “attached
2
to the city by the gods” (Ap. 28e), Socrates goes around Athens trying to persuade people
to care about the state of their souls and to live virtuously (Ap. 30b). It is in carrying out
this mission that we find him using the elenctic method to cross-examine interlocutors
(Ap. 29e-30a). And he makes it clear that he intends to do more than just show the
interlocutors that some of their beliefs are inconsistent. Socrates wants them to give an
account of the way they live their lives (R. I. 352d). 5 After all, by his lights, it is not that
unexamined beliefs are not worth having, but that “the unexamined life is not worth
living” (Ap. 38a).
Keeping this in mind, it should come as no surprise that we find Socrates insisting
that his interlocutors say only what they genuinely believe to be true. It is because he
wants the interlocutors to give an account of their lives that Socrates exhorts them never
to answer contrary to their real opinion. 6 Thus, on several occasions during the
dialogues—e.g. R. I, 346a & 350e, Pr. 331c, G. 495a-b & 500b, Cr. 49d—we find
Socrates admonishing the interlocutor to only say things they really believe. By his
lights, if an interlocutor is to give an account of his life, then he must say only things that
he genuinely believes to be true.
So, the “say what you believe” requirement serves at least two closely related
functions: On the one hand, by making this a guiding principle of the elenctic method,
Socrates helps distinguish his own method of cross-examination from the purely eristic
method of the Sophists—for whom the sole purpose of an argument is to win, regardless
of the truth of the respective positions. According to Socrates, one of the shortcomings
of eristic is that it seems wholly ineffective in persuading people that they ought to
devote themselves to wisdom and virtue (See, e.g., Eu. 277a-e). So, in order to avoid the
3
pitfalls of eristic and to distance himself from the Sophists, Socrates demands sincerity
from his interlocutors.
On the other hand, the requirement ensures that in refuting his interlocutors’
claims, Socrates will at the same time be reproaching them for the way they conduct their
lives. For, as we saw earlier, if the interlocutors have answered honestly—and answering
honestly is a necessary condition for giving an account of one’s life—then Socrates can
hold them accountable for both the answers they give and the lives they lead. This latter
reason is the primary motivation for Socrates’ refusal to proceed with premises that the
interlocutors don’t accept. After all, as Vlastos pointedly asks, “How could Socrates
hope to get you to give, sooner or later, an account of your life, if he did not require you
to state your personal opinion on the question under debate?” 7 Thus, in keeping true to
his maxim that the “unexamined life is not worth living,” Socrates imposes the “say what
you believe” requirement in order to insure that the interlocutors are forced to give an
account of their lives.
II: Waiving the Rule
If the analysis of the methods and goals of the elenchus presented in the preceding
section is correct, then it becomes difficult to understand why Socrates is ever willing to
dispense with the “say what you believe” requirement. And because the requirement
seemingly plays such a pivotal role in the elenctic method we should pay close attention
to the passages where Socrates either fails to enforce it or waives it altogether:
T1)
Socrates: “Nonetheless, we mustn’t shrink from pursuing the argument and looking into
this, just as long as I take you to be saying what you really think. And I believe that you
aren’t joking now, Thrasymachus, but are saying what you believe to be the truth.”
4
Thrasymachus: “What difference does it make to you, whether I believe it or not? It’s
my account you’re supposed to be refuting.” S.: “It makes no difference” ( R . I, 349a).
T2)
Thrasymachus (T): “So either allow me to speak, or, if you want to ask questions go
ahead, and I’ll say, “All right,” and nod yes and no, as one does to old wives' tales.”
Socrates (S): “Don’t do that contrary to your own opinion.” T.: “I’ll answer so as to
please you, since you won’t let me make my speech. What else do you want?” S.:
“Nothing by God. But if that’s what you are going to do, go ahead and do it. I’ll ask my
questions” ( R. I, 350e).
T3)
Socrates (S): “So, does someone who acts unjustly seem temperate to you in that he acts
unjustly?” Protagoras (P): “I would be ashamed to say that is so, Socrates, although many
people do say it.” S.: Then shall I address myself to them or to you?” Pr.: “If you like,
why don’t you debate the majority position first?” S.: “It makes no difference to me
provided you give the answers, whether it is your own opinion or not. I am primarily
interested in testing the argument, although it may happen both that the questioner,
myself, and my respondent wind up being tested” ( Pr. 333b-c).
T4)
Socrates (S): “What’s this Protagoras? Will you not say yes or no to my question?”
Protagoras (P): “Answer it yourself.” S.: “I have only one more question to ask you. Do
you still believe, as you did at first, that some men are extremely ignorant and yet still
courageous?” Pr.: “I think you just want to win the argument, Socrates, and that is why
you are forcing me to answer. So I will gratify you and say that, on the basis of what we
have agreed upon, it seems to me to be impossible” ( Pr. 360d-e)
T5)
Socrates: “As for you, do you join us in subscribing to the same opinion on these matters
or do you dissent from it?” Callicles: “No, I won’t dissent. I’m going along with you,
both to expedite your argument and to gratify Gorgias here” ( G. 501c).
T6)
Socrates: “Who else is willing? Surely we mustn’t leave the discussion incomplete.”
Callicles: “Couldn’t you go through the discussion by yourself, either by speaking in your
own person or by answering your own questions?” ( G. 505d-e)
5
Why would someone whose stated goal is to force the citizens of Athens to give an
account of their lives, ever allow them to say things that they do not truly believe—
especially when he has already admonished them earlier in the dialogue for being
insincere? Yet, as T1-T6 show, Socrates proceeds without the sincere assent of these
three interlocutors no less than six times—more times, in fact, than he invokes the
requirement in all of the dialogues . 8 Indeed, the only interlocutor who is actually held to
the requirement after having been informed of its importance is Crito.
Take, for instance, Socrates’ exchange with Thrasymachus. Given that Socrates
has already reprimanded him for saying things he doesn’t believe, when we hear
Thrasymachus ask, “What difference does it make to you, whether I believe it or not?
It’s my account you’re supposed to be refuting,” we understandably expect Socrates to
say that it makes all the difference . Especially given that, by Socrates’ lights, the primary
goal of the elenchus is to examine the interlocutors’ lives as well as their beliefs. Yet,
Socrates surprisingly says, “It makes no difference at all,” thereby explicitly waiving the
“say what you believe” requirement after having just invoked it . And this is not an
isolated case. Socrates behaves the very same way with Protagoras and Callicles, both of
whom give Socrates the answers he wants to hear solely and explicitly in an effort to
placate him and to appease the bystanders (See, e.g. T5 and T6). So, what sense are we
to make of these passages? Although T1-T6 have escaped the notice of most
commentators, Vlastos and Beversluis each offer explanations of why Socrates is
sometimes willing to proceed without his interlocutors’ sincere assent. Now we must
turn our attention to their accounts.
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin