The End Of Phenomenology - Expressionism In Deleuze And Merleau-Ponty.pdf

(108 KB) Pobierz
mawo422.dvi
Continental Philosophy Review 31: 15–34, 1998.
© 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
15
The end of phenomenology: Expressionism in Deleuze and
Merleau-Ponty 1
LEONARD LAWLOR
Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis, Memphis, Tennessee 38152, USA
The divine things hidden since the beginning of the world are
clearly perceived through the understanding of God’s creatures.
Romans 1:20
Probably stimulated by Levinas’s requirements for an ethics, the return to
the subject has fueled a renewed interest in classical phenomenology. As
Jean Greisch bluntly puts it, “after a period dominated by structuralism and
critique of metaphysics, a new generation of contemporary philosophers has
rediscovered phenomenology as a real possibility for thinking.” 2 Given this
“nouvelle vague phenomenologique” – Greisch includes many well-known
Merleau-Ponty scholars among his list of philosophers involved in “the new
phenomenological wave” – then what are we to make of the challenge to
phenomenology made in Sixties and Seventies in the name of structuralism
and post-structuralism? Has phenomenology met the challenge by means of
a more profound understanding of intersubjectivity, of the other? 3 Are we
now simply supposed to abandon the challenge? It seems to me that the
philosophy of Gilles Deleuze confronts phenomenology – of any ilk, from
Hegel to Maldinay – with its most powerful challenge, a challenge which
takes two forms.
On the one hand, there is the challenge of immanence. One can find this
challenge in Deleuze’s writings as late as What is Philosophy? (1991) and
as early as Empiricism and Subjectivity (1953). The challenge of immanence
states that there is no two world ontology, that being is said in only one way,
that essence does not lie outside of appearance; in short, the challenge of
immanence eliminates transcendence: God is dead. The challenge of imma-
nence, however, appears to be nothing less than the challenge with which
phenomenology confronts traditional metaphysics; the epoche is a process
in which one switches off the belief in things in themselves in order to ar-
rive at a plane of immanence: being is phenomenon. Despite this similarity,
Deleuze argues that phenomenology reinstates a dative; it relates the plane
86660212.001.png
16
LEONARD LAWLOR
of immanence back to a subject that constitutes the given. So, in What is
Philosophy? , Deleuze says, “Beginning with Descartes, and then with Kant
and Husserl, the cogito makes it possible to treat the plane of immanence
as a field of consciousness. Immanence is supposed to be immanent to a
pure consciousness, to a thinking subject.” 4 In Empiricism and Subjectivity ,
he says, “We embark upon a transcendental critique when, having situated
ourselves on a methodologically reduced plane that provides an essential
certainty...weask:howcantherebeagiven,howcansomethingbegivento
asubject,andhowcanthesubjectgivesomethingtoitself?...Thecritique
is empirical when, having situated ourselves in a purely immanent point of
view . . . we ask: how is the subject constituted in the given?” 5 The challenge
of immanence then is the challenge of empiricism, and this is why in What
is Philosophy? Deleuze suggests that the plane of immanence is a “radical
empiricism.” 6
On the other hand, there is the challenge of difference, which finds its
inspiration in Heidegger. In Difference and Repetition (1968), Deleuze says,
“According to Heidegger’s ontological intuition, difference must be articu-
lation and connection in itself; it must relate different to different without
any mediation whatsoever by the identical, the similar, analogous or the op-
posed. There must be a differentiation of difference, an in-itself which is
like a differentiator ,a Sich-unterscheidende , by virtue of which the differ-
ent is gathered all at once rather than represented on condition of a prior
resemblance, identity, analogy or opposition.” 7 The challenge then amounts
to this: according to its very notion, a ground must never resemble that which
it grounds. In other words, there must be a heterogeneity between ground
and grounded, between condition and conditioned. 8 According to Deleuze,
phenomenology does not meet the challenge of difference because the reduc-
tion moves the phenomenologist from natural attitude opinions or common
sense back to Urdoxa or primal faith. In What is Philosophy? , Deleuze says,
“Phenomenology wanted to renew our concepts by giving us perceptions
and affections that would make us give birth to the world, not as babies or
hominids but as beings, by right, whose proto-opinions would be the foun-
dations of this world. But we do not fight against perceptual and affective
cliches if we do not fight against the machine that produces them. By invok-
ing primordial lived-experience, by turning immanence into an immanence
to a subject, phenomenology could not prevent the subject from forming no
more than opinions that would already draw the cliche from new perceptions
and promised affections.” 9 The cliche would be a generality more eminent
or primal than any particular ( Urdoxa ), but a generality nonetheless under
which particulars could be subsumed; the machine is the subject drawing
resemblances out of perceptions, listening to the sense murmured by things.
THE END OF PHENOMENOLOGY
17
If we combine the two challenges, we must characterize Deleuze’s philos-
ophy, as he himself does in Difference and Repetition , with an oxymoronic
expression: “transcendental empiricism.” 10 Although this characterization sug-
gests a contradiction, in fact it does not. It is nothing less than the paradox of
expression. In Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (1968), Deleuze says,
“The paradox is that at once ‘the expressed’ does not exist outside of the
expression and yet bears no resemblance to it, but is essentially related to
what expresses itself as distinct from the expression itself.” 11 Expression
is the plane of immanence, which implies that the expressed does not exist
outside of it. But, having no resemblance to expression, the expressed, as the
essence of what expresses itself, is distinct from expression itself. According
to Deleuze, the expressed is “sense” ( sens ). 12 If sense is the key to Deleuze’s
double challenge to phenomenology, then we must privilege his 1969 Logic
of Sense . 13 In fact, Michel Foucault has already privileged this text, when he
says, in “Theatrum Philosophicum,” that “ The Logic of Sense can be read as
the most alien book imaginable from [Merleau-Ponty’s] The Phenomenology
of Perception .” 14 Foucault is undoubtedly correct. In The Phenomenology of
Perception , Merleau-Ponty defines the phenomenology of The Phenomenol-
ogy of Perception as “a study of the appearance of being to consciousness”; 15
thereby, he introduces the dative and relates the plane of immanence back to
consciousness. Moreover, Merleau-Ponty repeatedly appeals to a primordial
faith in order to ground knowledge; for instance, he says in “Others and the
Human World,” “My consciousness of constructing an objective truth would
never provide me with anything more than an objective truth for me, and
my greatest attempt at impartiality would never enable me to overcome my
subjectivity (as Descartes so well expresses it by the hypothesis of the evil
genius), if I had not, below my judgments, the primordial certainty of being
in contact with being itself, if, before any willful taking up of a position I
were not already situated in an intersubjective world, and if science too were
not supported by this originary doxa ” (PP 408/355). Nevertheless, The Phe-
nomenology of Perception isthetextinwhichMerleau-Pontysays,“...what
we have discovered through the study of motility is a new sense for the word
“sense.” The great strength of intellectualist psychology and idealist philos-
ophy comes from their having no difficulty in showing that perception and
thought have an intrinsic sense. ...The Cogito was the prise de conscience
of this inferiority. But all meaning was thereby conceived as an act of thought,
as the work of a pure I, and although rationalism easily refuted empiricism,
it was itself unable to account for the variety of experiences, for the element
of nonsense it, for the contingency of content” (PP 171–172/146–147). In
order to determine how alien The Logic of Sense is from The Phenomenology
of Perception , we must examine the relation of sense to nonsense in each. In
18
LEONARD LAWLOR
other words, in order to determine whether phenomenology – taking The Phe-
nomenology of Perception as an exemplary case – withstands the Deleuzian
double challenge, we must examine expression.
1. The transcendental field in Deleuze
The title, The Logic of Sense , comes from Hyppolite’s 1952 Logique et exis-
tence , which is a study of Hegel’s logic. 16 In Logique et existence , equating
the Hegelian concept with sense, Hyppolite explicitly defines Hegel’s logic as
a logic of sense. Recognizing the dependence of Hegel’s Logic on the earlier
Phenomenology of Spirit , Hyppolite describes Hegel’s phenomenology as the
generation of sense from the sensible. And finally, trying to demonstrate the
relevance of Hegel’s thought to the then contemporary philosophy, Hyppolite
describes the movement that leads to the logic of sense in Hegel as a “reduc-
tion” or as a process of “bracketing.” This is an obvious allusion to Husserl.
Given the influence that Hyppolite exerts on Deleuze – Deleuze, for instance,
dedicates his first book on Hume to Hyppolite 17 – we can see that, while
Deleuze does not call his philosophy a phenomenology (cf. LS 33/21), The
Logic of Sense takes place entirely under the sign of the phenomenological
reduction (cf. LS 123/101). Without the reduction, it would be impossible
for Deleuze to return to the surface, in other words, to the sensible, to the
appearances, to the phenomena, to the plane of immanence. As in all phe-
nomenology, Deleuze’s return to the surface does not imply the complete
elimination of the difference between appearance and essence; instead, as
Hyppolite would say, there is sense within the sensible. As Deleuze says,
“sense is the characteristic discovery of transcendental philosophy . . . it
replaces the old metaphysical Essences” (LS 128/105). 18 Deleuze’s project
therefore in The Logic of Sense is the determination of the donation of sense,
Husserl’s Sinngebung or sense-bestowal (LS 117/96, 87/69, 94/76; cf. DR
201/155). But unlike phenomenology, which turns the plane of immanence
into an immanence to consciousness which consists in an Urdoxa or gener-
alities through which the different kinds of belief are generated (LS 119/97),
Deleuze’s logic of sense is “inspired in its entirety by empiricism” (LS 32/20).
It is Sartre’s notion of an impersonal transcendental field that, according
to Deleuze, “restores the rights of immanence,” frees immanence from being
immanent to something other than itself, and turns phenomenology into “a
radical empiricism.” 19 The transcendental field therefore, must correspond,
Deleuze says, to the conditions that Sartre laid down in his “decisive” 1936
The Transcendence of the Ego (LS 120/98–99). 20 The transcendental ego,
according to Sartre, is unnecessary for the unification of objects, 21
for the
unification and individuation of consciousness, 22
and is itself moreover a
THE END OF PHENOMENOLOGY
19
constituted object. 23 Therefore the transcendental field must be conceived
as an absolutely impersonal or non-personal consciousness; 24 it would be
equivalent to what Hyppolite in 1957 would call a “subjectless transcendental
field.” 25 As impersonal and non-individuated, the transcendental field, for
Deleuze, consists in the “they” or the “one” ( l’on ) (LS 178/152). But this
“das Man” is not equivalent to what is expressed in common sense or in
doxa . The phrase “everyone recognizes that,” for example, does not express
Deleuze’s “they,” because there is always, according to Deleuze, a “profound,
sensitive conscience” who does not recognize what everyone else claims to
recognize (DR 74/52). This sensitive conscience is a “sensitive point,” a point
of tears and joy, sickness and health, hope and anxiety, a turning point, a bot-
tleneck, a boiling point. The transcendental field, therefore, consists in such
sensitive points, in what Deleuze calls “singularities” or “anti-generalities”
(LS 121/99).
Because of the connection to Merleau-Ponty, which we are trying to pre-
pare, it is important here to note what Deleuze (and Guattari) say in A Thou-
sand Plateaus : “It seems to us that Husserl brought thought a decisive step
forward when he discovered a region of vague and material essences (in other
words, essences that are vagabond, anexact and yet rigorous).” 26 Immediately
after this comment Deleuze (and Guattari) connect Husserl’s vague morpho-
logical essences to their own notion of singularities. This connection implies
that what Deleuze calls singularities in The Logic of Sense are at least related
to if not equivalent to what Husserl calls “eidetic singularities” in Ideas I ;
eidetic singularities are material essences, which have species and genera
(and thus generality) over them, but have no particularizations under them
(see Ideas I , #12). In other words, eidetic singularities are essences of, that is,
generated from, facts. This connection between Deleuzian singularities and
Husserlian eidetic singularities is significant for our purposes because Husserl
utilizes the notion of an eidetic singularity in his late fragment The Origin of
Geometry , a text which Merleau-Ponty studied carefully.
The most precise definition of singularities, however for Deleuze, lies in
the context of expression, which in The Logic of Sense refers to Husserl
as well, Husserl’s Ideas I , paragraph #124: 27 singularities are that which is
expressed in an expression or that which is perceived in a perception, in a
word, sense (LS 32/20). From Husserl’s notion of sense, Deleuze extracts
two characteristics: neutrality and sterility. A singularity is sterile because,
as Husserl says, and Deleuze quotes this from paragraph 124, “the stratum of
expression is not productive.” Sterility then means that a singularity is nothing
more than an incorporeal double of the expression or of what is perceived (LS
97–98/78–79, 146–151/122–125). Describing the existence of such idealities,
Deleuze says that sense is an “extra-being” or a “phantasm” (LS 17/7). To
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin