Weigand -Argumentation; The Mixed Game.pdf

(296 KB) Pobierz
590218168 UNPDF
Argumentation (2006) 20:59–87
Springer 2006
DOI 10.1007/s10503-006-9000-4
Original Paper
Argumentation: The Mixed Game
Edda Weigand
Arbeitsbereich Sprachwissenschaft
Universita¨tMu ¨ nster
Fachbereich 9, Bispinghof 2B
Mu¨nster, D-48143
Germany
E-mail: weigand@uni-muenster.de
ABSTRACT: The paper introduces a new model of argumentation, the Mixed Game
Model, that no longer separates rule-governed competence from actual performance
but starts from human beings and their ability of competence-in-performance. Human
beings are able to orientate themselves in ever-changing surroundings and to negotiate
diverging views in argumentative action games. Argumentation is thus described as a
mixed game played by human beings according to principles of probability. These
principles include constitutive, regulative and executive principles. Constitutive Prin-
ciples focus on the basic components of the game, that is, action, dialogue, and
coherence as the interplay of different communicative means. Regulative Principles
mediate between correlated human abilities and interests. Executive Principles guide
the sequencing of action according to cognitive strategies. The mixed game no longer
rests on pre-established harmony but describes performance as a non-equilibrial pro-
cess of negotiation that mediates between order and disorder and is based on the
integration of various parameters such as rationality, reason, persuasion and emotion.
How the model works is exemplified by an analysis of part of a debate in the
European Parliament.
KEY WORDS: argumentation, competence-in-performance, dialogue, action games,
speech act theory, rationality, reason, emotion, persuasion, rhetoric
1. THE STATE OF THE ART
In the field of argumentation research, the object-of-study ‘argumenta-
tion’ is either reduced to the lines of rationality and reason or it is
claimed to be a process of persuasion. In recent years, such a separa-
tion of rational thinking and persuasion has been unmasked as ‘Des-
cartes’ error’ by experimental neurological results (e.g., Damasio
2000). However, we do not even need neurology to recognize this
truth about human abilities. An unprejudiced look at human behav-
iour demonstrates that rationality and reason cannot be separated
from persuasion. Such an open look, not biased by tradition, requires
60
EDDA WEIGAND
us to say good-bye to classical models and to face the challenge of
integration in modern theorizing which is issued to science in general,
from cosmology to biology and the humanities, i.e. the challenge of
mediating between order and disorder, between general rules and
individual particularities. According to Prigogine (1997, p. 7), ‘science
is no longer identified with certitude and probability with ignorance...
We are observing the birth of a science that is no longer limited to
idealized and simplified situations but reflects the complexity of the
real world’.
The type of rational rhetoric based on argumentative logic is essen-
tially influenced by Toulmin’s book on ‘The uses of argument’ (1958)
even if Toulmin emphasises that it is not logical but practical reason
that counts in human life. In his recent book ‘Return to reason’, he
draws our attention to the turning point of modern theorizing with the
issue of ‘living with uncertainty’ (Toulmin 2001, p. 204): ‘The price of
living in the world of the pragmatists and the skeptics is the need to
acknowledge that our best-founded beliefs are still uncertain.’ However,
his concept of ‘practical reason’ or ‘balance of reason’ does not reach
real life but is limited by the norm of ‘a Reasonableness that combines
intellectual force in content with a moderation of manner’ (p. 21f.).
Moreover, it needs to be more closely linked to verbal interaction.
The persuasive type of New Rhetoric, mainly put forth by Perelman
(e.g., 1977), brings us a bit nearer to dialogue although it is again put
in syllogistic form. The claims and their arguments are not interac-
tively combined. Even if we stress the point of persuasion and the
adherence of the audience, we are still a long way from real dialogues.
The concept of the audience’s adherence remains within the scope of
the speaker who aims at adherence. Dialogue however means interac-
tion between speaker and interlocutor. Acting and reacting are the
minimal constituents of the dialogic action game. New Rhetoric there-
fore has to be freed from its monologic standpoint and be transformed
into a proper dialogic approach (cf. Weigand 1999).
In recent decades, the claim that ‘argument is a form of communica-
tion’ has been emphasised (Willard 1989, p. 12). There seem to be two
lines of approach to argumentation as dialogue, a more empirical,
conversational one, directed to performance, and a more theoretical,
rule-guided one, directed to competence. Kallmeyer’s ‘Gespra¨ chsrheto-
rik’ (1996) belongs to the empirical type insofar as it takes its method-
ological basis from Conversational Analysis which requires us to start
with recording and transcribing authentic dialogues (p. 10). Kallmey-
er’s ‘Gespra ¨ chsrhetorik’ represents more a programme, exemplified by
a series of studies, than an elaborated theory. As a programme it
includes interesting guidelines that go beyond an exclusively formal
approach. The same is true of the ‘discourse analytic approach’ by
ARGUMENTATION: THE MIXED GAME
61
Jacobs and Jackson (1982) who also start from a collection ‘of a set of
naturally occurring arguments’ and proceed to constructing fruitful
hypotheses.
The theoretical type of approach, on the other hand, gives priority
to rules and structures (cf., e.g., Moeschler 1985; Plantin 1996; Cattani
2001; Stati 2002). An outstanding model in this regard is the pragma-
dialectic approach by van Eemeren and his group (e.g., van Eemeren
2001; van Eemeren and Grootendorst 2004). Pragma-Dialectics com-
bines Aristotelian logic with categories of speech act theory. ‘Funda-
mental to a pragma-dialectical analysis is that it is based on a
‘mariage de raison’ between normative insights and descriptive insights
in the argumentative use of language’ (van Eemeren and Grootendorst
2004, p. 110). Even in analysing everyday conversation, the focus lies
on the reconstruction of a normative level, an underlying competence
of ‘critical discussion’. Rhetoric as strategic manoevring is included
(van Eemeren and Houtlosser 1999). The technique of reconstruction
can be considered as an attempt at reconciling the level of competence
with that of performance.
Dascal and Gross (1999) make another attempt at ‘reconciliation’
between competence and performance by combining Aristotelian rheto-
ric and Gricean pragmatics in an approach called ‘The marriage of
pragmatics and rhetoric’. It remains an exclusively theoretical
approach that is not exemplified by naturally occurring examples.
On the other hand, successful performance is the object-of-study
within the tradition of practical philosophy. The sophists, for instance,
were aware of the fact that in performance ‘anything goes’, that the
inferior case can be made the superior one by using the right means
and strategies. Rhetoric of this type is still alive and proliferates in
numerous publications dealing with popular rhetoric which provide
recipes for all contingencies beyond any ethical restriction.
This short sketch of the state of the art in argumentation theory
highlights the basic question of how to bridge the gap between compe-
tence and performance, theory and practice, rationality and persua-
sion. Competence and performance are terms in theory, and we have
to ask ourselves whether the separation they imply is useful in order to
come to grips with the issue of modern theorizing, namely ‘living with
uncertainty’. I will address this issue from two perspectives, the
descriptive perspective of the Mixed Game Model (MGM) and the
normative perspective of Pragma-Dialectics (PD).
2. THE DESCRIPTIVE VERSUS THE NORMATIVE VIEW
Living with uncertainty does not mean that we are the victims of the
complex. On the contrary we are able to orientate ourselves in
62
EDDA WEIGAND
ever-changing surroundings. We use rules as far as they go, and we
orientate ourselves by means of principles of probability when rules
come to an end. There is no simple as such nor complex as such. The
central reference point are human beings and their abilities. It is our
competence-in-performance that enables us to master the complex. In
this respect I would like to recall what Martinet (1975, p. 10) told us
about the relationship between object and methodology, namely ‘not
to sacrifice the object’s integrity to methodological exigencies’. If the
object of the theory is human competence-in-performance, the meth-
odology has to guarantee its integrity, i.e. not to separate what is inte-
grated by human nature and learned or acquired capacities. A key
premise for a descriptive theory of the Mixed Game therefore is:
• MGM Describing actual behaviour must not contradict human
nature and learned or acquired capacities.
In contrast to the MGM, Pragma-Dialectics leaves competence and
performance separate at two levels and tries to ‘reconcile’ them by
‘reconstruction’. This key term, as I see it, has a double sense. On the
one hand, it is used for ‘reconstructing the implicit argumentation that
one needs to understand in order to grasp the message conveyed’ (van
Eemeren and Grootendorst 2004, p. 114f.). In this sense it aims at
understanding and implies a separation of what is explicitly said and of
what is to be inferred. What is separated here, however, is integrated
by human nature. Speaking and implying are integrated abilities used
as communicative means, verbal and cognitive ones, in the mixed
game. We simply mean more than we say. On the other hand, if it is
not ‘possible to reconstruct the communicative act in question as an
implicit or indirect speech act, adhering to the Communicative Princi-
ple and the rules of language use’, reconstruction is meant as ‘a trans-
formation in the interest of reasonableness’ based on the ‘normative
background of a pragma-dialectical analysis’. In this sense, reconstruc-
tion ‘converts what is empirically possible into what is normatively
desirable for the sake of reasonableness’.
The term ‘reconstruction’ thus has a descriptive and a normative
face. It is meant as an ‘effort to describe argumentation as it is, but
with respect to an image of how it should be’ (van Eemeren et al.
1993, p. xi):
• PD Describing actual behaviour includes the reconstruction of
norms of reasonableness.
In my view, however, a theory cannot make descriptive and norma-
tive claims at the same time. It is basically this normative claim that
distinguishes PD from the MGM. Reconstruction of norms is to be
considered a technique of theory not of life. In life we know norms,
we do not have to reconstruct them. They can however not be
ARGUMENTATION: THE MIXED GAME
63
conceived of as an innate part of human nature. Whether we keep to
them is up to us. In contrast to the descriptive view, which is based on
human nature, the normative view claims a specific way of behaviour
as it should be, the way of what is called ‘critical discussion’.
Even if ‘norms of critical discussion’ in PD are meant to be instru-
mental, not ethical norms, they are not only formal conventions but
rely on a specific ideological background. In this respect we also have
to tackle the issue of ethical norms. Much as I agree with claims for a
human civilized behaviour, ethical claims are beyond the reach of a
descriptive theory and can only be added as an appeal or recommen-
dation. It is true that we can assume that human beings have an
awareness of such norms – and that makes up the framework of a
normative theory – but it is equally true that their actions do not al-
ways comply with these norms – and that makes up the framework of
the mixed game. A normative theory is legitimate as such, i.e. as a the-
ory that serves as a benchmark for evaluating practice or performance.
Such a benchmark cannot be gained by empirical analyses of perfor-
mance. It has to be set up either by norms justified by some underly-
ing ideology or by collective acceptance. It is these norms we refer to,
for instance, in speech acts of reproaching such as you are always very
late. In the same way ‘reasonable’ or ‘civilized’ behaviour can be
called upon in institutional settings. A different benchmark is set up
by the criterion of ‘effective’ action in everyday life or in institutions.
Over and above norms, it is personal or institutional interests that
determine what is considered to be ‘effective performance’.
The descriptive model does not set up norms of ‘good’or‘reasonable’
behaviour. It distinguishes between different ways of behaviour, among
them what could be called civilized behaviour which can be expected and
even demanded by everyday and institutional conventions. Conventions
however are not yet norms. A descriptive model describes human action
and behaviour. Insofar as human beings consider conventions to be
norms and feel obliged to keep to them, the theory has to include this
technique of accepting norms as a technique of orientation. Here we
have arrived at the point where PD and the MGM meet: norms become
guidelines of behaviour that have to be included in the MGM by describ-
ing them, i.e. not by claiming them to be fulfilled. Techniques of orienta-
tion in general are thus to be described as principles of probability that
are based on rules, conventions, norms and individual inferences as well.
Ethics as a normative discipline is however excluded.
To sum up: It is mainly two issues that have to be focused on in
descriptive research on argumentation, the dialogic issue of a consis-
tent speech act theory of dialogue and the integrational issue of a new
way of theorizing that goes beyond separating levels and starts with
the complex of the ‘mixed game’ from the very outset.
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin