Asimov, Isaac - Robot City 3 - Cyborg.pdf

(433 KB) Pobierz
162815529 UNPDF
B
B
Isaac Asimov's Robot City Book 3: Cyborg
ISAAC ASIMOV'S
ROBOT
CITY
BOOK 3: CYBORG
WILLIAM F. WU
Copyright © 1987
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Special thanks for help in writing this novel are due to David M.
Harris, Michael P. Kube-McDowell, Rob Chilson, Alison Telure, my
parents, Dr. William Q. Wu and Cecile F. Wu, and Plus Five Computer
Services, Inc.
This novel is dedicated to
Laura J. Lehew
who always remains very special
CYBERNETIC ORGANISM
ISAAC ASIMOV
A robot is a robot and an organism is an organism.
An organism, as we all know, is built up of cells. From the molecular
standpoint, its key molecules are nucleic acids and proteins. These
float in a watery medium, and the whole has a bony support system. It
is useless to go on with the description, since we are all familiar with
organisms and since we are examples of them ourselves.
A robot, on the other hand, is (as usually pictured in science fiction)
an object, more or less resembling a human being, constructed out of
strong, rust-resistant metal. Science fiction writers are generally
chary of describing the robotic details too closely since they are not
usually essential to the story and the writers are generally at a loss
how to do so.
The impression one gets from the stories, however, is that a robot is
wired, so that it has wires through which electricity flows rather than
tubes through which blood flows. The ultimate source of power is
either unnamed, or is assumed to partake of the nature of nuclear
power.
What of the robotic brain?
When I wrote my first few robot stories in 1939 and 1940, I imagined
a “positronic brain” of a spongy type of platinum-iridium alloy. It was
162815529.002.png
B
B
platinum-iridium because that is a particularly inert metal and is
least likely to undergo chemical changes. It was spongy so that it
would offer an enormous surface on which electrical patterns could
be formed and un-formed. It was “positronic” because four years
before my first robot story, the positron had been discovered as a
reverse kind of electron, so that “positronic” in place of “electronic”
had a delightful science-fiction sound.
Nowadays, of course, my positronic platinum-iridium brain is
hopelessly archaic. Even ten years after its invention it became
outmoded. By the end of the 1940s, we came to realize that a robot's
brain must be a kind of computer. Indeed, if a robot were to be as
complex as the robots in my most recent novels, the robot brain-
computer must be every bit as complex as the human brain. It must be
made of tiny microchips no larger than, and as complex as, brain
cells.
But now let us try to imagine something that is neither organism nor
robot, but a combination of the two. Perhaps we can think of it as an
organism—robot or “orbot.” That would clearly be a poor name, for it
is only “robot” with the first two letters transposed. To say “orgabot”,
instead, is to be stuck with a rather ugly word.
We might call it a robot-organism, or a “robotanism”, which, again, is
ugly, or “roborg”. To my ears, “roborg” doesn't sound bad, but we
can't have that. Something else has arisen.
The science of computers was given the name “cybernetics” by
Norbert Weiner a generation ago, so that if we consider something
that is part robot and part organism and remember that a robot is
cybernetic in nature, we might think of the mixture as a “cybernetic
organism”, or a “cyborg”. In fact, that is the name that has stuck and
is used.
To see what a cyborg might be, let's try starting with a human
organism and moving toward a robot; and when we are quite done
with that, let's start with a robot and move toward a human being.
To move from a human organism toward a robot, we must begin
replacing portions of the human organism with robotic parts. We
already do that in some ways. For instance, a good percentage of the
original material of my teeth is now metallic, and metal is, of course,
the robotic substance par excellence .
The replacements don't have to be metallic, of course. Some parts of
my teeth are now ceramic in nature, and can't be told at a glance from
the natural dentine. Still, even though dentine is ceramic in
appearance and even, to an extent, in chemical structure, it was
originally laid down by living material and bears the marks of its
origin. The ceramic that has replaced the dentine shows no trace of
life, now or ever.
We can go further. My breastbone, which had to be split
longitudinally in an operation a few years back, was for a time held
together by metallic staples, which have remained in place ever since.
162815529.003.png
B
B
My sister-in-law has an artificial hip-joint replacement. There are
people who have artificial arms or legs and such non-living limbs are
being designed, as time passes on, to be ever more complex and
useful. There are people who have lived for days and even months
with artificial hearts, and many more people who live for years with
pacemakers.
We can imagine, little by little, this part and that part of the human
being replaced by inorganic materials and engineering devices. Is
there any part which we would find difficult to replace, even in
imagination?
I don't think anyone would hesitate there. Replace every part of the
human being but one—the limbs, the heart, the liver, the skeleton,
and so on—and the product would remain human. It would be a
human being with artificial parts, but it would be a human being.
But what about the brain?
Surely, if there is one thing that makes us human it is the brain. If
there is one thing that makes us a human individual, it is the intensely
complex makeup, the emotions, the learning, the memory content of
our particular brain. You can't simply replace a brain with a thinking
device off some factory shelf. You have to put in something that
incorporates all that a natural brain has learned, that possesses all its
memory, and that mimics its exact pattern of working.
An artificial limb might not work exactly like a natural one, but might
still serve the purpose. The same might be true of an artificial lung,
kidney, or liver. An artificial brain, however, must be the precise
replica of the brain it replaces, or the human being in question is no
longer the same human being.
It is the brain, then, that is the sticking point in going from human
organism to robot.
And the reverse?
In my story “The Bicentennial Man”, I described the passage of my
robot-hero, Andrew Martin, from robot to man. Little by little, he had
himself changed, till his every visible part was human in appearance.
He displayed an intelligence that was increasingly equivalent (or even
superior) to that of a man. He was an artist, a historian, a scientist,
an administrator. He forced the passage of laws guaranteeing robotic
rights, and achieved respect and admiration in the fullest degree.
Yet at no point could he make himself accepted as a man. The sticking
point, here, too, was his robotic brain. He found that he had to deal
with that before the final hurdle could be overcome.
Therefore, we come down to the dichotomy, body and brain. The
ultimate cyborgs are those in which the body and brain don't match.
That means we can have two classes of complete cyborgs:
a) a robotic brain in a human body, or
b) a human brain in a robotic body.
We can take it for granted that in estimating the worth of a human
being (or a robot, for that matter) we judge first by superficial
162815529.004.png
B
B
appearance.
I can very easily imagine a man seeing a woman of superlative beauty
and gazing in awe and wonder at the sight. “What a beautiful
woman,” he will say, or think, and he could easily imagine himself in
love with her on the spot. In romances, I believe that happens as a
matter of routine. And, of course, a woman seeing a man of
superlative beauty is surely likely to react in precisely the same way.
If you fall in love with a striking beauty, you are scarcely likely to
spend much time asking if she (or he, of course) has any brains, or
possesses a good character, or has good judgment or kindness or
warmth. If you find out eventually that good looks are the person's
only redeeming quality, you are liable to make excuses and continue
to be guided, for a time at least, by the conditioned reflex of erotic
response. Eventually, of course, you will tire of good looks without
content, but who knows how long that will take?
On the other hand, a person with a large number of good qualities
who happened to be distinctly plain might not be likely to entangle
you in the first place unless you were intelligent enough to see those
good qualities so that you might settle down to a lifetime of happiness.
What I am saying, then, is that a cyborg with a robotic brain in a
human body is going to be accepted by most, if not all, people as a
human being; while a cyborg with a human brain in a robotic body is
going to be accepted by most, if not all, people as a robot. You are,
after all—at least to most people—what you seem to be.
These two diametrically opposed cyborgs will not, however, pose a
problem to human beings to the same degree.
Consider the robotic brain in the human body and ask why the
transfer should be made. A robotic brain is better off in a robotic body
since a human body is far the more fragile of the two. You might have
a young and stalwart human body in which the brain has been
damaged by trauma and disease, and you might think, “Why waste
that magnificent human body? Let's put a robotic brain in it so that it
can live out its life.”
If you were to do that, the human being that resulted would not be the
original. It would be a different individual human being. You would
not be conserving an individual but merely a specific mindless body.
And a human body, however fine, is (without the brain that goes with
it) a cheap thing. Every day, half a million new bodies come into
being. There is no need to save anyone of them if the brain is done.
On the other hand, what about a human brain in a robotic body? A
human brain doesn't last forever, but it can last up to ninety years
without falling into total uselessness. It is not at all unknown to have a
ninety-year-old who is still sharp, and capable of rational and
worthwhile thought. And yet we also know that many a superlative
mind has vanished after twenty or thirty years because the body that
housed it (and was worthless in the absence of the mind) had become
uninhabitable through trauma or disease. There would be a strong
162815529.005.png
B
B
impulse then to transfer a perfectly good (even superior) brain into a
robotic body to give it additional decades of useful life.
Thus, when we say “cyborg” we are very likely to think, just about
exclusively, of a human brain in a robotic body—and we are going to
think of that as a robot.
We might argue that a human mind is a human mind, and that it is the
mind that counts and not the surrounding support mechanism, and
we would be right. I'm sure that any rational court would decide that
a human-brain cyborg would have all the legal rights of a man. He
could vote, he could be enslaved, and so on.
And yet suppose a cyborg were challenged: “Prove that you have a
human brain and not a robotic brain, before I let you have human
rights.”
The easiest way for a cyborg to offer the proof is for him to
demonstrate that he is not bound by the Three Laws of Robotics.
Since the Three Laws enforce socially acceptable behavior, this
means he must demonstrate that he is capable of human (i.e. nasty)
behavior. The simplest and most unanswerable argument is simply to
knock the challenger down, breaking his jaw in the process, since no
robot could do that. (In fact, in my story “Evidence”, which appeared
in 1947, I use this as a way of proving someone is not a robot—but in
that case there was a catch.)
But if a cyborg must continually offer violence in order to prove he
has a human brain, that will not necessarily win him friends.
For that matter, even if he is accepted as human and allowed to vote
and to rent hotel rooms and do all the other things human beings can
do, there must nevertheless be some regulations that distinguish
between him and complete human beings. The cyborg would be
stronger than a man, and his metallic fists could be viewed as lethal
weapons. He might still be forbidden to strike a human being, even in
self-defense. He couldn't engage in various sports on an equal basis
with human beings, and so on.
Ah, but need a human brain be housed in a metallic robotic body?
What about housing it in a body made of ceramic and plastic and fiber
so that it looks and feels like a human body—and has a human brain
besides?
But you know, I suspect that the cyborg will still have his troubles.
He'll be different. No matter how small the difference is, people will
seize upon it.
We know that people who have human brains and full human bodies
sometimes hate each other because of a slight difference in skin
pigmentation, or a slight variation in the shape of the nose, eyes, lips,
or hair.
We know that people who show no difference in any of the physical
characteristics that have come to represent a cause for hatred, may
yet be at daggers-drawn over matters that are not physical at all, but
cultural-differences in religion, or in political outlook, or in place of
162815529.001.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin