Pragmatism, Neopragmatism, And Phenomenology - The Richard Rorty Phenomenon.pdf

(71 KB) Pobierz
78120351 UNPDF
c 1997 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
95
Review essay
Pragmatism, Neopragmatism, and Phenomenology: The Richard
Rorty Phenomenon
BRUCE WILSHIRE
Department of Philosophy, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903, U.S.A.
What was it that Nature would say? – R.W. Emerson
The world does not speak. Only we do – Richard Rorty
Traditionally, the chief function of every civilization has been to orient its
members in the world. Time proven ways of getting about and surviving are
imparted ritualistically, ways of avoiding confusion, damage, disaster, ways
perchance of flourishing. Revolutions of all sorts in the last four hundred
years have relentlessly disrupted or destroyed nearly all traditional maps of
the world and modes of orientation. The very meaning of “civilization” has
become problematical. As has “reason” and “reasonable.” To understand the
emergence of pragmatic modes of thinking in the last half of the last century
requires an understanding of the ground swell of crisis to which it is a creative
response. Also required is a grasp of the connections between pragmatism and
phenomenology. I then turn to a current literary phenomenon: Richard Rorty’s
so-called neo-pragmatism, and his assiduous avoidance of phenomenology.
Finally, a note about the ecological crisis, and how a deeper attunement to the
environment calls for a reappropriation of phenomenological impulses in the
earlier pragmatism.
Every traditional civilization aims to orient its members within their imme-
diate locality. This is true even when interpretations of local things and events
are in terms of a “spirit realm” or “alternate reality” – construals fantastic to
contemporary North Atlantic ears. Always a modicum of what we would call
“common sense” is discernable, e.g., a tree may be experienced as moving
under certain conditions and for certain modes of numinous consciousness,
butitisjust that tree, the one that is always found in the work-a-day-world
forty paces in front of the chief elder’s house. Without commonsensical
rootage in the local environment, elementary evaluations necessary for the
orientation and conduct of everyday life are impossible.
Now it is just this rootage that 400 years of revolutions of all sorts have
disrupted. Western industrialization uprooted vast populations from agrari-
Human Studies 20: 95–108, 1997.
96
BRUCE WILSHIRE
an forms of life in which time proven routines and rituals integrated with
Nature’s regenerative cycles gave life purpose and direction. Euro-American
science and technology produce marvels of aggressive movement that very
quickly overrun the world, dislocating and destroying countless civilizations,
and causing strain and dislocation within Euro-American civilization itself.
Technological advances outpace structures of interpretation within which they
can be evaluated.
Just a few examples of how traditional guidance systems, rules of thumb
and proverbs, become obsolete: “As right as rain.” But since the rain in many
sections is so acidified from burning fossil fuels that it kills fish in lakes
and streams, what is right about it? “Practice makes perfect.” But if steroids
injected in athletes allow them to outperform others who practice diligently
but don’t take them, what becomes of our maxim? A psycho-active pill may
eliminate grief over the death of a loved one. But what if this also eliminates
grieving and its traditional expressions, that closure that opens the way to
new birth? Breaking out of the life-ways that allow us to evaluate them, our
technological means of control may have gone permanently out of control.
The most cursory notice of the upsurge of modern European science and
philosophy in the 17th century reveals the abrupt departure from traditional
feelingful, orientation-laden, commonsensical local knowledge. Reach back
2000 years; contrast this to Artistotle. For all his sophistication and intellectual
power, he presupposed the commonsensical life-world of the time. To learn
about things is to make judgments about those characteristics commonly
thought to be essential to them, and about those accidental traits which may
be altered yet the beings remain themselves: e.g., their location in geo-cultural
space they happen to occupy at the time (if they are moveable beings), or their
mode of dress, for example, or their more or less passing emotional states –
but states typed, understood, and settled from time immemorial.
Contrast this to the skepticism of the 17th century scientist-philosopher
Descartes. He assumes that the world is not as commonsense describes its
traditional, myth-laden sensorial richness. (How can we trust the senses,
Descartes asks, when the sun merely appears to move across the sky, and its
disc merely appears small enough to be covered by a coin held before the
eye). For him the physical world is only as mechanistic mathematical physics
describes it: a vast collection of contiguous objects exhibiting only such
clinical and feelingless properties as extension, shape, mass, acceleration,
force. Having thus reduced and objectified the “outer world,” he turns “within”
and objectifies a non-extended domain which he thinks is mind: private and
personal consciousness, a kind of container in which float such personal
qualities as feelings, tones, colors, smells, sensations of various kinds, mere
appearances. No longer the moral, aesthetic, or spiritual qualities of things in
PRAGMATISM, NEOPRAGMATISM, AND PHENOMENOLOGY
97
the immediately apparent world, they are reduced to being psychical qualities
merely. The gain from this caustic way of thinking repays the loss, he thinks:
one certitude : I think therefore I am. At least he can know he is “a thing that
thinks.”
On every level or parameter – from the most abstruse domain of philosoph-
ical and scientific theory to revolutionary political, economic, and world-
historical events – modern European civilization shifts off its basis in local,
sensuous knowledge and traditional modes of feeling and evaluation. Kant
noted with alarm that two essential, intertwining strands of civilization –
science and morality – unravelled. If only the observations of mechanis-
tic science reveal the “external” world reliably, and badness or evil are not
observable properties of things, then the judgment, say, Rape is bad is not
really knowledge. It reveals nothing about who we essentially are as beings-
human who must find our way and survive and perchance flourish in the vast
world, but is merely a venting of our subjective negative sentiments – feelings
and preferences that we happen to have been conditioned to feel in a particular
culture, but that we might do without.
*
*
*
Try to imagine the inception of the 19th century: the French Revolution
reducing itself to chaos and despotism is just the most obvious disruption of
traditional local ways. That century opens with titanic efforts to reweave the
fabric of civilization, to conceive the world at such a primal, originative level
that science and technology and every other revolution can be reintegrated
with local knowledge and emotional-evaulational life – ways of living deeply
rooted in the history, even prehistory, of human survival and flourishing on
earth. This is the matrix within which pragmatic modes of thought emerged
in the second half of the last century.
Schelling and Hegel launch a vast critique of European philosophy. They
realize that they root within its flood plain; but its channel must be radically
deepened if its wandering currents are to be collected into one sustaining flow.
We must, they think, get beyond seventeenth century “scientific realisms”
which take for granted bases of judgment that should be thematized and
superceded through reflection. Without this, civilization will continue to dis-
integrate – “facts” coming unhinged from “values” in endless “future shock”
– for we will not grasp intertwining principles of thought, action, feeling, and
being that are sustaining and orienting in any local environment.
Where does Descartes stand , what does he assume, when he objectifies
the world in terms of mechanistic physics, takes an aspect of the world for
98
BRUCE WILSHIRE
the whole? And where does he stand when he objectifies mind as a private
container full of physical entities, takes the psychical aspect of mental life for
the whole? Answer: he stands on the whole processual natural and cultural
world, and the whole communal minding and knowing of it within which he
was born, and in which he participates every instant, and which allows him
to make the objectifications, individuations, abstractions, and reductions that
he makes. He assumes the ordinary world in which we live, and this he does
not acknowledge.
Hegel in the nineteenth century writes that mind is not like a lens that might
fatally distort an “external world;” Descartes’ doubts are concocted, artificial.
For to imagine a world external to mind is already to use the mind! No, for a
world to be a world , an intelligible whole, minding must be something that the
world does. The world’s evolution is the development of its ever deepening
coming home to itself, its self-comprehension, as that energy which is mind
or spirit ( Geist ). As Schelling writes, it is “the holy and continuously creative
energy of the world which generates and busily evolves all things out of
itself,” comprehending them in the very process of evolving them. It follows
that truths, facts, concerning what satisfies the deepest human potentialities
and hungers, given our place in the evolving whole, are simultaneously values.
With Schelling and Hegel, local, rooted, sense experience and evaluation seem
to be rewoven with scientific research and cosmic speculation and reverence;
reason achieves a new flexibility, resourcefulness, daring, and civilization
seems on the verge of recovery (at least in thought).
*
*
*
Charles Peirce, William James, and John Dewey – the paradigmatic Amer-
ican pragmatists – are inundated and deeply rooted in this so-called idealist
tradition. They cannot accept the notion of Absolute Mind or Spirit ( Geist ),
particularly as Hegel left it: the sanguine belief that since the universe is One,
there must be one Mind working in and through it all, and that we can enter
into this working and discover its continuously world-creating dialectical log-
ic – philosophizing a reverential act in which “we think God’s thoughts after
Him.” But – but – the idealists’ critiques of modern “realisms” are accepted.
To allow philosophical thought to make unexamined assumptions in order to
begin is to countenance partial views, aspects, and abstractions to pass as the
whole, and this is to abet fragmentation, disorientation, frightened and aggres-
sive restlessness. Particularly damaging is Cartesian dualism which pictures
Nature as a machine. How could we feeling beings, capable of tradition, ever
fit into this? The very time in which Europeans used their mechanical model
PRAGMATISM, NEOPRAGMATISM, AND PHENOMENOLOGY
99
and their tools to overwhelm the globe, they lost all sense of being rooted
sustainingly in Nature, and all appreciation of indigenous peoples’ profound
contentments.
How is philosophical thought to begin authentically? It must somehow be
self-starting and self-validating. This can only mean that we must start with
where we actually find ourselves here and now in the local environment.
We find ourselves within the circumpressure of things as they appear to us.
Appearing things that can no longer be denigrated as mere appearances, for
they compose the primal tissue of meaning without which no other mean-
ing can be made, without which all deliberate inquiry, analysis, reflection,
research, and technology is impossible. And in fact when we describe these
appearances closely we see they hold within themselves connective tissue.
Any local environment presents itself within a horizon of the immediately
sensible – audible, visible, smellable, touchable – and every horizon points
both inwards at this and beyond itself to everything else – whatever exactly the
universe might be. The earlier pragmatism retained in broad outline organi-
cist assumptions: at all levels of analysis parts are parts-of-wholes, organs of
the whole organism, and their well-functioning is for the sake of the whole.
And organisms at all levels are wholes-of-parts that feed back into the parts,
feeding and sustaining them for their allotted time within the whole.
That is, 19th and early 20th century pragmatisms are simultaneously phe-
nomenologies, attempts to describe the primal birth of phenomena or appear-
ances within our experience in such a way that the basic categories for weaving
together and interpreting the whole world are discerned. For the original prag-
matists meaning and truth are “what works” in the sense that they function to
weave together aworld in our experience. We must believe whatever is nec-
essary to achieve this whole. Pragmatists’ idea of what “works” has been, and
in many quarters still is, misunderstood, because of a scandalous ignorance
of the history of philosophy, of the matrix within which their ideas grow.
The misunderstanding at its crassest goes like this: “Pragmatists believe that
meaning and truth are whatever makes you happy to believe.”
No, ideas have a life of their own, they are strands of activity that either
interweave with the rest of the world as they predict in their very meaning they
will, or they do not. How this happens to make us feel as individuals is irrele-
vant (unless the ideas are about our feelings themselves). Misunderstandings
of original pragmatism typically spring from Cartesian abstractions from the
whole experienceable world that forget this experienceable whole, and, with-
out grasping how any objectification is possible, objectify and demarcate
minds as private individual containers with ideas and other mental contents –
like feelings of satisfaction – floating inside them.
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin